Page 254 - Encyclopedia of Philosophy of Language
P. 254
Reference
and pure denotation views. What determines the ref- erence of a name is not an implied descriptive content but an appropriate relation between users of the name and some individual to whom the name was originally given. So the account essentially has two components: the first postulating an initial 'baptism' of an indi- vidual with a name, the second explaining how the name gets transmitted through a community and across time. On the first, Kripke holds that an object may be named ('baptized') either by ostension or by the use of a description (e.g., the first puppy to be born will be called X); but 'fixing the reference' by means of a description is not equivalent to 'giving the mean- ing' of the name (one thinks here of Mill's example of Dartmouth). As for transmitting the name from per- son to person, all that is required, at least on Kripke's account, is an intention on the part of users to refer to the same object as the person they learnt the name from. Thus a 'chain' is set up that links users of the name with the object originally named. That chain determines what is referred to.
Of course, as described, the chain is by no means merely a sequence of external causal relations, inde- pendent of human thought processes. Among those who have developed causal theories there are those, like Kripke and Evans (1973), who acknowledge a role at least for 'intention' in the transmission of names, and those, like Devitt (1981), Devitt and Sterelny (1987), and in a qualified manner Donnellan (1966), who seek a 'purer' or more external form of causal linkage. J. R. Searle (1983) has objected that causal theories, especially those of Kripke and Don- nellan, turn out to be just variants of descriptivist theories in that they presuppose an essential role for intentional contents both in reference fixing and in transmission. Searle, in defending descriptivism, argues that in practice names become associated with richer kinds of intentional content than merely 'para- sitic' kinds like 'the same object as so-and-so referred to.'
Although strict causal theorists like Devitt and Sterelny see themselves following in the footsteps of Mill, they acknowledge that there is more to the mean- ing of a name than just its denotative role. By a curious replay of history, they reintroduce the idea of 'sense' as well as reference, albeit not quite as Frege described it. Sense now becomes a 'designating chain' making up a 'network' connected with each name. The informativeness of identity statements like Dr Jekyll is Mr Hyde is explained in terms of the distinct causal networks underlying the two names. Significantly, sev- eral other philosophers (McDowell 1984; Forbes 1990) have sought to defend neo-Fregean accounts of sense, as applied to proper names, within a broadly causal framework.
10. Conclusion
The debate between descriptivist and causal theories of names has not been finally resolved, though there
might be some convergence as implied by the revised versions of sense theories. Certainly the issues are clearer now than in the work of Mill and even Russell. Furthermore, Kripke's work, and also Putnam's (1975), has shown how questions about proper names can be extended to other terms in language, par- ticularly natural-kind terms, where causal theories have led to a radical reappraisal of ancient debates about essentialism.
See also: Indexicals; Reference: Philosophical Issues; Russell, Bertrand.
Bibliography
Devitt M 1981 Designation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL
Devitt M, Sterelny K 1987 Languageand Reality: An Intro- duction to the Philosophy of Language. Basil Blackwell, Oxford
Donnellan K1966 Reference and definite descriptions. Philo- sophical Review75: 281-304
Evans G 1973 The causal theory of names. Proceedings of the AristotelianSociety suppl. vol. 47: 187-208
Evans G 1982 The Varieties of Reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Forbes G 1990 The indispensability of Sinn. Philosophical Review 99: 535-63
Frege G 1892 On the sense and reference. In: Geach P, Black M (eds.) 1952 Translationsfrom the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege. Basil Blackwell, Oxford
Irvine A, Wedeking G A 1993 (eds.) Russell and Analytic Philosophy. University of Toronto Press, Toronto
Kripke S 1972 Naming and necessity. In: Davidson D, Har- man G (eds.) Semantics of Natural Language. Reidel, Dordrecht
Kripke S 1977 Speaker's reference and semantic reference. In: French P, Uehling T, Wettstein H (eds.) Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN
McDowell J 1984 De Re senses. Philosophical Quarterly 35: 98-109
Mill J S 1970 A System of Logic. Longman, London
Neale S 1990 Descriptions. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA Putnam H 1975 Mind. Languageand Reality: Philosophical
Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Quine W V O 1953 From a Logical Point of View. Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA
Russell B 1905 On denoting. Mind 14: 479-93
Russell B 1919 Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.
Allen and Unwin, London
Searle J R 1958 Proper names. Mind 67: 166-73
Searle J R 1979 Attributive and referential. In: Expression
and Meaning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Searle J R 1983 Intentionally. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge
Strawson P F 1950 On referring. Mind 59: 320-44
Strawson P F 1974 Subject and Predicate in Logic and Gram-
mar. Methuen, London
Wittgenstein L 1961 (transl. Pears D, McGuinness B) Trac-
tatus Logico-Philosophicus. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London
232