Page 4 - Webb_(2010)
P. 4

Cambridge Journal of Education   329

              refuses to recognise a separation between the cognitive and affective domains of human
              existence and regards hope, like knowledge, as an experience of the entire body,
              involving emotions, desires, dreams, thought processes and intuitions (Freire, 1993,
              p. 90; 2007b, p. 94). Far from being a learned (or not learned) thinking pattern, hope
              for Freire is ‘an essential component’ of the human condition such that ‘it is impossible
              to exist without it’ (1998a, p. 69; 1994, p. 72). Crucially, as a phenomenon that is always
              and already present in the human condition, the role of education is not conceived as
              one of instilling hope but rather of evoking it and providing it with guidance.
                 One need not adopt an overly undifferentiated notion of ‘continental philosophy’
              to see that his understanding of hope as an ontological dimension of the human condi-
              tion places Freire within this tradition. Whereas debates within analytical philosophy
              tend on the whole to treat hope as a ‘desiderative–calculative’ activity (Godfrey, 1987)
              comprising a desire plus a probability estimate (Day, 1991), philosophers such as
              Bloch (1995), Marcel (1962), Pieper (1997) and Sartre (1996) regard hope as the driv-
   Downloaded by [210.57.214.154] at 23:56 16 February 2015
              ing force of human life, propelling us along the path to ourselves. Freire belongs
              firmly in the latter camp, being far less concerned to analyse probability estimates
              pertaining to individual hopes (espoir) than to study and evoke the more fundamental
              hope (espérance) that makes individual hopes possible and gives them meaning.
                 The notion of homo viator is significant here, both within Freire’s work and within
              the philosophy of hope more generally. This notion of the itinerant condition of exist-
              ence, of the human being as traveller or wayfarer, is neatly summarised by John
              Macquarrie when he claims ‘that man is not yet himself and is on the way to fulfilment
              of what he has in him to become’ (1978, p. 23). In this condition of status viatoris
              (Pieper, 1997, p. 91), as we continually travel ‘the path to ourselves’ (Bloch, 1995,
              p. 934), ‘being necessarily means “being-on-the-way”’ (Marcel, 1962, p. 11) and
              ‘man is taken to be a wayfarer… always and essentially en route’ (Dauenhauer, 1986,
              pp. 6–7). Each of these themes is incorporated into Freire’s conceptualisation of
              humans as ‘unfinished’ beings (1998a, p. 51), ‘beings in the process of becoming’
              (1972b, pp. 56–57), conscious of their incompleteness and their status as travellers,
              seekers, searchers, pilgrims.
                 Hope is of fundamental importance in all of this. For Freire, humans are ‘eternal
              seekers. Eternal because of hope’ (1998a, p. 58). Without hope, humans would despair
              in the face of their unfinishedness and would become immobilised. It is hope that acts
              as the ‘necessary impetus in the context of our unfinishedness’, ‘stimulating the
              pilgrim’ and ‘leading the incessant pursuit of humanity’ (Freire, 1998a, p. 69; 1985,
              p. 127; 1972b, p. 64). It is hope, in other words, that drives us ever onwards as travellers,
              wayfarers, seekers, in pursuit of completeness. And it is in this pursuit of completeness,
              this hope-driven search that characterises the human condition, that the necessity and
              necessarily political nature of education is to be found. For because we search, we are
              driven to explore, interrogate, question and learn, thus becoming educable. Indeed, ‘the
              matrixes of hope are matrixes of the very educability of beings, of human beings’
              (Freire, 2007a, p. 87). And because we are unfinished, and thus become as we learn,
              the education rendered necessary by our educability attains its political character:

                 The real roots of the political nature of education are to be found in the educability of the
                 human person. This educability, in turn, is grounded in the radical unfinishedness of the
                 human condition and in our consciousness of this unfinished state. (Freire, 1998a, p. 100)
   1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9