Page 124 - A Little Life: A Novel
P. 124

Laurence smiled back at him and nodded. “Very good,” he said.
                   “Well, I  have  a  question,”  said  Harold,  who’d  been  quiet,  listening  to
                them. “How and why on earth did you end up in law school?”

                   Everyone laughed, and he did, too. He had been asked that question often
                (by Dr. Li, despairingly; by his master’s adviser, Dr. Kashen, perplexedly),
                and he always changed the answer to suit the audience, for the real answer
                —that he wanted to have the means to protect himself; that he wanted to
                make  sure  no  one  could  ever  reach  him  again—seemed  too  selfish  and
                shallow  and  tiny  a  reason  to  say  aloud  (and  would  invite  a  slew  of
                subsequent questions anyway). Besides, he knew enough now to know that

                the law was a flimsy form of protection: if he really wanted to be safe, he
                should  have  become  a  marksman  squinting  through  an  eyepiece,  or  a
                chemist in a lab with his pipettes and poisons.
                   That night, though, he said, “But law isn’t so unlike pure math, really—I
                mean, it too in theory can offer an answer to every question, can’t it? Laws
                of anything are meant to be pressed against, and stretched, and if they can’t

                provide solutions to every matter they claim to cover, then they aren’t really
                laws  at  all,  are  they?”  He  stopped  to  consider  what  he’d  just  said.  “I
                suppose the difference is that in law, there are many paths to many answers,
                and in math, there are many paths to a single answer. And also, I guess, that
                law isn’t actually about the truth: it’s about governance. But math doesn’t
                have to be convenient, or practical, or managerial—it only has to be true.
                   “But  I  suppose  the  other  way  in  which  they’re  alike  is  that  in

                mathematics,  as  well  as  in  law,  what  matters  more—or,  more  accurately,
                what’s more memorable—is not that the case, or proof, is won or solved,
                but the beauty, the economy, with which it’s done.”
                   “What do you mean?” asked Harold.
                   “Well,”  he  said,  “in  law,  we  talk  about  a  beautiful  summation,  or  a
                beautiful judgment: and what we mean by that, of course, is the loveliness

                of not only its logic but its expression. And similarly, in math, when we talk
                about  a  beautiful  proof,  what  we’re  recognizing  is  the  simplicity  of  the
                proof, its … elementalness, I suppose: its inevitability.”
                   “What about something like Fermat’s last theorem?” asked Julia.
                   “That’s a perfect example of a non-beautiful proof. Because while it was
                important that it was solved, it was, for a lot of people—like my adviser—a
                disappointment. The proof went on for hundreds of pages, and drew from

                so many disparate fields of mathematics, and was so—tortured, jigsawed,
   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129