Page 383 - Deep Learning
P. 383

366                         Conclusion

            constant across contexts and tasks, shared by all individuals (variations along
            a few quantitative parameters aside) and stable over time, at least in relation
            to the duration of individual cognitive processes. The architecture is presum­
            ably innate. in this view, variability in task performance across tasks, across
            individuals and over time is accounted for by variations in the knowledge that
            is applied in any one performance. unification is served – and this is newell’s
            fundamental innovation – by the fact that the same set of basic processes is used
            to explain every cognitive phenomenon. simplicity is served because the basic
            processes and their modes of combination can be stated relatively concisely.
            The  complexity that is squeezed out of the basic machinery bulges out in the
            specification of the knowledge that the cognitive architecture applies to gen­
            erate behavior. The soar theory by newell, J. laird and P. s. Rosenbloom and
            the ACT­R theory proposed by Anderson and co­workers are two attempts to
            propose specific theories of the form that newell envisioned, but other theo­
                                                                14
            rists have proposed models of the cognitive architecture as well.  no proposal
            has won wide acceptance, but the search for the right specification of the cog­
            nitive architecture is the only theoretical programme in cognitive psychology
            that provides a clear vision of what a final theory of human cognition might
            look like.
               The research strategy followed in this book departs from the cognitive
            architecture programme. The subject of this book is not human cognition.
            i believe that the latter is too vast and ill­defined a target for theory forma­
            tion.  To  illustrate,  consider  whether  dreaming  is  a  cognitive  phenomenon.
            on what grounds would it be excluded? Dreaming appears to be a process
            of  manipulating  mental  representations,  the  very  stuff  of  cognition.  But  if
            dreaming is included among bona fide cognitive phenomena, then no contem­
            porary theory of the cognitive architecture stands any chance of being even
            approximately correct. We are too far from understanding the alterations in
            consciousness during the wake­sleep cycle, let alone the function of dreaming.
            similarly, a complete theory of cognition should explain the role of emotions
            in cognition, the distinction between meaning and reference in language and
            the digital­to­analogue conversion that presumably occurs somewhere on the
            path from decision to movement. These and other research problems are so far
            from being solved that proposing theories of human cognition is premature.
               The work reported in this book follows the alternative strategy of focusing
            on a single, particularly interesting cognitive phenomenon: non­monotonic
            cognitive change. People demonstrably undergo such changes and the goal
            of explaining them poses theoretical challenges that are significantly different
            from those of explaining stable performance or monotonic learning. The first
   378   379   380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388