Page 108 - Composing Processes and Artistic Agency
P. 108

Orchestrating different forms of knowledge  97

            their interaction, fine-tuning and manner of complementing and completing
            one another are important as well. And all the elements that constitute mastery
            cannot be represented exhaustively because they cannot be analysed and
            comprehended in their entirety. We observe, therefore, that composing has
            two levels of achievement: the work being created and the artistic practical
            knowing that has been generated. The new artistic practical knowing may be
            helpful to composers in future composing situations. Proficiency in composing
            is not a static state, but a dynamic process that cannot be concluded. It
            remains fragile because it is linked to an appraising field of practice that itself
            is in constant flux. We therefore understand proficiency to be fundamentally
            social, meaning that it is interdependent on the societal organisation of the
            artistic practice concerned.


            3.3 Forms of knowledge in composing processes: an interpretative order
            Frequently (but not always), composing processes contain complex tasks that
            indicate challenging achievements. This is why these creative processes often
            take months. During that time, various work modes occur: intuitive and
            reflective, exploratory and systematic. In this section, we will be using a plural
            concept of knowledge to explain agency in composing. This concept encom-
            passes jointly generated contents and abilities that can be learned and trans-
            formed. Additionally, the meaning and value of any kind of knowledge are
            negotiated socially. Appreciation and success therefore depend not only on a
            person’s knowledge or artistic achievement, but also on collective processes
            within the art world. However, we want to clarify that we do not posit any
            causal relation between forms of knowledge and agency or mastery. A person’s
            real performance exceeds the identifiable or assumed knowledge that scholars
            ascribe to him or her. In other words, the concept of knowledge cannot
            answer all questions concerning human agency (see Zembylas & Dürr 2009:
            125–130, 141–146). Nevertheless, we consider a differentiated concept of
            knowledge to be useful for three reasons. First, it replaces opaque concepts
            such as talent, and musicality, and individualistic attributes such as intelli-
            gence and creativity. Second, it demystifies complex and demanding achieve-
            ments without trivialising them because it requires practical knowledge (in the
            sense of proficiency), commitment, experience and insight. Third, it embeds
            agency in a collective practice without masking or marginalising individual
            qualitative differences in performance.
              Drawing on the concepts of knowledge proposed by John Dewey, Gilbert Ryle
            and Michael Polanyi, we can contrast two basic forms: 1) artistic practical forms
            of knowledge (Figure 3.1), among which we count knowledge of work processes,
            situative knowledge and body knowledge; 2) formal propositional forms of
            knowledge (Figure 3.2), including scholarly knowledge, local knowledge and
            formal technical compositional knowledge. This subdivision is for analytical
            purposes. In the observable processes of composing all forms of knowledge
            always appear in a dynamic mutual relationship and as an amalgam.
   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113