Page 112 - Composing Processes and Artistic Agency
P. 112

Orchestrating different forms of knowledge  101

              Second, musicians speak of “fingers’ knowing” (see also Sudnow 1978/
            2001: 18, 71, 79); a great many of the composers we interviewed referred to it
            as well. They sit at the piano, and their fingers tell them whether a sequence
            of notes feels good or whether a given passage can be played – in physiological
            terms, this is known as body or muscle memory. But beyond this, there is
            knowledge of other bodies, too. Composers consider the performing musicians
            who, during the concert, might “like to show their virtuosity” or should not
            “be annoyed the whole time” by an extremely difficult sequence of notes. The
            concept of body knowledge therefore also has an inter-subjective facet. Merleau-
            Ponty calls this inter-corporeality: “It is through my body that I understand
            other people, just as it is through my body that I perceive things” (Merleau-
            Ponty 1945/2005: 216; see also Gallagher 2014: 10–16). Composers try out
            things using their own bodies and have a common musical practice, so they
            develop a shared bodily implementation of experiences. This common body
            enables composers to anticipate the body perspective of musicians whilst they
            are composing (see Gebauer 2009: 97–101).


            3.3.2 Formal propositional forms of knowledge
            It would be grossly negligent to overlook the composers’ broad cultural
            knowledge or to underestimate its significance for their composing practice.
            All the composers we met are frequent and intensive listeners, have a sound
            knowledge of the historical and contemporary repertoires of their music culture,
            are well-informed about contemporary discourses in music theory and concern
            themselves with a broad spectrum of texts from various disciplines. Their
            explicable knowledge is not merely academic theoretical knowledge, but relevant
            in several ways. One composer described pieces of music and books that
            inspire him as “sockets” into which he plugs. In certain situations, he “charges
            his batteries” with music or philosophical thoughts to generate ideas for his
            pieces. This kind of cultural knowledge does not lack practical relevance since
            it is simultaneously a product of and a prerequisite for participating in a cultural
            practice. It supplies a semantic framework that gives, for instance, a certain
            meaning to the structural relationship between individual notes or associates
            musical quotations and stylistic elements with a certain aesthetic. Codified cultural
            knowledge is, as Paul Duguid (2005: 114) points out, “remarkably powerful,
            but its power is only realised through the corresponding knowing how”.The
            relevant, practice-based “knowing how” denotes not just the understanding of
            semantic meaning but also the understanding of how relevant a particular
            knowledge is in a given situation. Formal propositional knowledge, however, is
            not genuinely practical because it is not a direct prerequisite for agency in
            composing. That agency also requires domain-specific, artistic practical knowing.
              Scholarly knowledge (see Figure 3.2) refers to contents that are system-
            atically collected, discussed, verified and evaluated. Generally, scholarly
            knowledge is deemed to consist of (preliminarily) justified true beliefs whose
            validity is always provisional and bounded by paradigms. Composers
   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117