Page 115 - Composing Processes and Artistic Agency
P. 115

104  Orchestrating different forms of knowledge

                […]. “Seeing” in such situations is anything but a matter of perceiving
                discrete sense data, collecting them and then synthesising them. […]For
                that we need to have a set of categories and concepts drilled into us, if we
                are to orient ourselves. This conceptual orientation is precisely what we
                receive in the course of our professional enculturation.
            The conceptual orientation that evolves through enculturation is not only
            intellectual, but also linked to acquired sensorimotor skills (see Noë 2012:
            25f.). Wittgenstein (1953/1968: § 19, 23, 304; 1967: § 532–534) views it in the
            context of practical rules, examples and analogies (see Williams 1999: 200f.).
            Anthropologically speaking, humans are quintessentially shaped by the symbolic
            means that they themselves have created and use. As Charles Taylor (2006:
            32) writes, it is virtually impossible to draw a clear boundary here:

                It is not only that any frontier is porous, that things explicitly formulated
                and understood can “sink down” into unarticulated know-how, in the
                way that Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus [1986] have shown us with learning,
                that our grasp on things can move as well in the other direction, as we
                articulate what was previously just lived out. It is also that any particular
                understanding of our situation blends explicit knowledge and unarticulated
                know-how.

            Similarly, analytic propositions cannot be clearly demarcated from synthetic
            propositions, nor formal propositional knowledge from artistic practical
            knowing (see also Quine 1951; Lakoff & Johnson 1999: 19f.). We therefore
            want to emphasise the following: first, composers’ formal propositional
            knowledge is not simply theoretical and abstract, but intrinsically interwoven
            with other sensory and motor skills. Second, the oscillation between a flow of
            action and a conscious distancing from the material – in other words, between
            the intuitive and the reflective work mode – is a typical trait of complex and
            challenging activities, such as composing.
              Consequently, we regard music-aesthetic theories and musicological elements
            not as “external objects” at all, but as systems of beliefs entangled with
            musical practices. Under certain circumstances, some of them might be con-
            ducive to experimental approaches; others might reinforce canonical ideas
            associated with traditional trajectories. Thus, generally speaking, we argue
            along with Juniper Hill (2012: 87ff.) that music theories and aesthetic ideas
            may encourage or inhibit musical activities and, consequently, we consider
            them to be conditions that afford agency. While being educated and having
            broad propositional knowledge is not evidence of mastery, the two forms of
            knowledge – propositional and artistic practical – cannot be uncoupled. As
            Jeff Coulter (1989: 15f.) states:

                Knowing what people are doing (including oneself) is knowing how to
                identify what they are doing in the categories of a natural language,
   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120