Page 74 - Constructing Craft
P. 74

more important as a means of defining who was a craftsperson and who was a craft

               artist.  Thinking about the relationship of craft to art before the studio craft
               movement flourished was often informed by the Kantian notion ‘that an aesthetic

               experience could be supported only by an autonomous art object, and that the
               disinterested gaze of the art spectator is elicited only when art is removed from

                                                                           10
               moral, social and religious values and from ordinary life.’  Craft, through its
               association with ordinary life and functionality, could not be an autonomous art

               object. This concept of the independent aesthetic experience excluded function –

                                                                                                    11
               ‘and thus much of craft ‒ from the possibility of having an aesthetic component.’
               The distinction led philosophers and scholars not only to neglect craft as a subject
               of study but also to devalue the role of craft in art.






               The Aesthetic Theory of Art



               Robin George Collingwood

               An example of a philosopher who thought about art and craft in this way was Robin

               George (R. G.) Collingwood. Collingwood, a British historian and philosopher, could
               clearly present an argument separating craft from art. To achieve this he employed

                                             12
                                                                      13
               the ideas of Immanuel Kant  and Benedetto Croce  that stated that the only
               purpose of art was the expression of feelings and beauty and, in addition, only the
               artist can decide if that has been achieved. Craft conversely, according to

               Collingwood, was ‘the power to produce a preconceived result by means of
                                                             14
               consciously controlled and directed action.’  He disentangled craft from art proper
                                                                         15
               by offering six reasons why there existed a distinction.  ‘Proper’ has been
               emphasised because it was through this word that Collingwood distinguished most

               emphatically the difference between art and craft. Art ‘proper’ divided the modern

               use of the word art from its ancient meaning – craft. Collingwood was offering his
               advice on art and craft in the late 1930s when the studio craft movement in Britain

               was at an early stage in its development and most craft conformed to his criteria.
               Nonetheless, some thought Collingwood had misunderstood the role of craft and

               furthermore, his description of craft was no longer relevant in the second half of the



                                                                          Constructing Craft
   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79