Page 36 - Edo: Art in Japan, 1615–1868
P. 36

48
                             their work and worry chiefly  about hiding things from  their superiors."  "The  way of the  world nowa-
                             days," he further  observed, "is to go about doing things, making haste.... [Everyone] temporizes, which
                             means that, in order to avoid incurring the  displeasure of their self-indulgent superiors, it is thought
                             that the  right thing to do for underlings is to run  about, scurrying around with a stern mien, which is
                             why everything and  everyone hustles about in such a hurry." 49




          F O R M  AS  N O R M  The emphasis  on form that so often  produced the  empty formalism decried by Sorai may to  some
                             degree be related to the  outmoded military model according to which Tokugawa society was  structured.
                             Correct form  is preeminently  a theatrical quality of precise mimesis, and  one encounters it in  the                 35
                             theater, the  army, or bureaucracy. The Muromachi-period founder of no theater, Zeami (1363 -1443),
                             theorized, however, that perfect outward form  does not constitute  the flower of artistic performance
                                                                                                         50
                             unless  it is animated by a special quality that  the  actor has  to bring out from  within.  It was the ab-
                             sence  of such  an inner state of being that Sorai regretted. Since ritual and  rites  are one form  of theater,

                             Confucian  etiquette  also emphasizes that  observance of form  ought to be preceded and  accompanied
                             by the  properly cultivated mind. Thus, by extension, the  mind  also expresses  itself through  the pre-
                             scribed forms of cultural practices such  as calligraphy, the  tea  ceremony, or flower arrangement, which
                             were all in vogue among commoners in late Tokugawa Japan.
                                    A number  of thinkers  in eighteenth-century Japan minimized the  inner component, ultimately
                             to the point of disappearance. In Sorai's opinion, the inner quality that should  accompany ritual behav-
                             ior (in the  widest possible sense as standardized forms of social interaction) could not be developed
                             independently  from  ritual form  itself. The right pattern  of social interaction, which was fixed by ritual,
                             produced the right kind of mind-set. The best learning, he argued, was the kind that dispensed  with
                             words and occurred through the whole body, from  things and situations, thus  producing the proper
                                                  51
                             habits  and dispositions.  Put more generally, matter  properly patterned  would produce a properly
                             patterned  mind, and consequently a properly mannered human being.
                                    The spiritual concerns of Sorai's student  Dazai Shundai (1680 -1747) were even further limited,
                             for  they stopped  at the behavioral level. All one had  to do was to act in the  prescribed way, no  matter
                                                         52
                             what  one's inner state  of mind;  external conformity was the  only thing that  counted for him. External
                             forms, which choreographed  social interaction, were the  most important if not the  only thing  human
                             beings had in common. These forms were expected to channel human  emotions  and sentiments  into
                             cultured patterns  that constituted  the basis for human communication. To be uncivilized (or not human)
                             was to lack such forms. Many influential Tokugawa thinkers argued that humans  had  not much in

                             common  otherwise. Contrary to what  Song Confucians  emphasized  endlessly in their  discourse on
                             human  nature, these thinkers  denied the  existence  of a common nature that all humans  would  share.
                                    For example, Confucians  who relied on Mencius argued that the  mind of all humans  is alike:
                             "All palates  enjoy the  same  tastes,  all ears the  same  sounds, all eyes the  same beauty. Should only
                                                            53
                             minds  not share  the  same  things?"  Mencius argued for sameness  based  on an everyday, "obvious"
                             consensus  regarding sensory experiences. Sorai opposed this in order to privilege difference. "People
                                                                                         54
                             differ  in their  natures; their minds  are [as different]  as their  faces."  Why assume  that unseen  reality
                             differs  from  what  strikes  the  senses?
   31   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   40   41