Page 50 - Deep Learning
P. 50

The Nature of the Enterprise              33

            contains one suggestive clue: There are no traces of physical representations –
            cave paintings, bone carvings, stone sculptures, wood models  – before the
                                      22
            appearance of our own species.  For example, Homo erectus, widely believed
            to be one of our ancestor species, existed for over a million years without leav-
            ing  any  physical  representations  behind.  The  archeological  remains  of  the
            Neanderthals,  our  enigmatic  relatives  and  co-existents,  are  similarly  bereft
            of pictures and statues. But the archeological remains of our own species are
            replete with multiple forms of physical representations. Both the famous cave
            paintings in the Chauvet and Cosquer caves in the south of France and the old-
            est known carved figurines are approximately 30,000 years old. Archeological
            finds in southern Africa push the beginnings of representation perhaps as far
            back as 100,000 years ago, close to the emergence of modern humans.
               It is tempting to hypothesize that the ability to represent mentally and the
            ability to represent overtly evolved in parallel. After all, how could someone
            draw a bison on a cliff face inside a pitch black, torch-lit cave unless he had the
            ability to visualize the bison? If internal and external representations evolved
            in parallel, the lack of pre-human representational artifacts might indicate that
            other hominid species, including the Neanderthals, did not represent, and the
            capability to represent thus emerges as a decisive evolutionary advance. The
            human species might have been born on the day when a person for the very
            first time deliberately created a likeness, a physical object that was not valued
            for what it was but for its capacity to stand for something else. Once the abil-
            ity to create representations, internal and external, was established, it came
            under strong selective pressure to better support memory, reasoning, planning
            and other cognitive functions, perhaps providing Homo sapiens with a decisive
            competitive advantage over the now conspicuously extinct Neanderthals. 23


                                  Functions and Processes

            The traditional form of scientific analysis aims to understand a natural sys-
            tem – the circulatory system, say, or an ecosystem – by picking it apart and
            figuring out how the parts are related. Because minds are not physical entities,
            it has always been unclear how to apply scientific analysis in psychology. How
            do we decide what the parts are? Once upon a time, psychologists hoped to
            be able to identify the parts of the mind by rolling their eyeballs 180 degrees
            inward and introspect, but this method turned out to be unworkable; research-
            ers could not agree on what they saw in there. One might expect the parts of
            the mind to correspond, one-to-one, to parts of the brain, but this turns out
                                                                       24
            not to be the case. Phrenology is no longer considered a viable theory,  and
   45   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55