Page 60 - Composing Processes and Artistic Agency
P. 60

The topography of composing work  49

            interpretation and at the same time leave much implicit. The relation between
            music notation and sound event remains underdetermined. It has to be prac-
            tically revealed, tried and negotiated through playing. While Carl Dahlhaus
            (1970: 65 – our translation) states that “the reading of sheet music […]is
            always accompanied by acoustic imaginings”, this is neither entirely true nor
            completely false. Acoustic imaginings do not have the sensory concreteness of
            sound events because they always contain vagueness. They consist of acoustic
            impressions that those reading the score already have in their aural memory
            from previous experiences. That can be the only explanation of why, for every
            piece of music, there is always a spectrum of different interpretations that are
            deemed legitimate by a community of shared cultural practice.
              If we define scores as the outcomes of intentional acts because they are
            primarily aimed at performers, then there must be case-specific criteria for
            success. The writing and finalising of scores is then an activity that requires
            various competences to meet these criteria. Performing musicians read the score
            by starting with the notation signs and then channelling towards the musical
            meaning. The directionality of their reading is crucial. It has an underlying
            aesthetic intentionality even in the absence of any intended musical meaning –
            for instance, in Dadaistic concepts – and even where composers try to be
            illegible by deliberately including discontinuities, polyvalent marks and allit-
            erations. Both reading and writing are procedural acts, which implies that they
            weigh potential meanings. Importantly, this includes implicitly taking into
            account those aspects which cannot be represented through a given notation
            system. All composers are aware of the multi-layeredness and ambiguity of
            writing processes and reading. Clemens Gadenstätter approaches the issue
            pragmatically and with a relaxed attitude: “[Helmut] Lachenmann”,hesays,
            developed a fantastic notation system, “and I don’t see any reason to re-invent
            the wheel when it’s already great. […] Anyway, one thing’s obvious: there’sno
            such thing as a perfect notation.”


            1.4.3 Algorithms and software
            Previous sections have repeatedly demonstrated that it is now impossible to
            imagine the practice of composing without technical apparatuses, and espe-
            cially without computers with specific programs. The importance of algo-
            rithms in this cannot be denied, either. However, our empirical material on
            the topic is too limited. Consequently, we will address the subject only briefly,
            with a few fundamental reflections on the significance of algorithms for the
            practice of composing.
              Algorithms existed long before modern computers were invented and have
            been used in various ways in composition processes. Historically, we know of
            algorithmic approaches from the Middle Ages onwards, and in 1787 Mozart
            invented a musical dice game. It is only from the 1950s onwards, however,
            that they gained in importance (see Essl 2007). Algorithms are formal
            instructions or calculation models for generating, processing, transforming
   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65