Page 342 - Data Science Algorithms in a Week
P. 342

Explorations of the ‘Transhuman’ Dimension of Artificial Intelligence   323

                       index  of  the  ‘transhuman’  ontological  status  of  Samantha  as  OS  (or  AI),  where
                       ‘transhuman’ is a category denoting an entity wholly ‘beyond’ the human as encountered
                       in experiential reality. In this respect the present use of the term differs from the use of
                       ‘transhuman’ as an epithet for a stage of human development beyond its ‘natural’ state, to
                       one where human beings would, according to Kurzweil (2006) increasingly ‘fuse’ with
                       technology (for example as conceived and practised by the performance artist, Stelarc,
                       who believes that “the human body is obsolete”; see Stelarc under References). In the
                       narrative context of the film such ‘transhumanism’ does not seem out of place, of course,
                       but it might be wholly disconcerting if an AI were to inform one of this fundamentally
                       different ontological aspect of its mode of being in the course of what could conceivably
                       become routine conversations between humans and artificially intelligent beings such as
                       operating systems (of which the fictional Samantha is one). Even in the case of robots
                       this  ontological  difference  would  obtain,  because  arguably  the  relationship  between  a
                       robot’s ‘body’ (conceived by some as ‘hardware’), on the one hand, and its ‘mind’ (or
                       ‘software’), on the other, is not at all the same as that between a human’s mind and body.


                                                     MIND AND BODY


                          With  the  thought-provoking  depiction  of  the  (possible,  if  not  probable)  differences
                       between human and AI consciousness by Jonze, above, in mind, one can remind oneself that
                       one obvious angle from which these differences can be approached, is that of the relationship
                       between the human mind and body – something that has occupied philosophers at least since
                       the  father  of  modern  philosophy,  René  Descartes,  bequeathed  his  notorious  17th-century
                       metaphysical ‘dualism’ of (human) body and mind to his successors. For Descartes (1911) the
                       mind  was  a  different  “substance”  compared  to  the  body  –  the  former  was  a  “thinking
                       substance” and the latter an “extended substance”, and he resolved the problem of the manner
                       in which these mutually exclusive substances interacted by postulating the so-called “animal
                       spirits”  –  a  hybrid  concept,  denoting  something  between  mind  and  body  –  as  mediating
                       between them in the pineal gland at the base of the human brain.
                          Increasingly, from the late 19th-century onwards, thinkers started questioning the validity
                       of such dualistic thinking; in various ways philosophers such as Friedrich Nietzsche, Edmund
                       Husserl, Martin Heidegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Jean-Francois  Lyotard argued that
                       humans cannot be broken down into mutually exclusive parts, but that they comprise beings
                       characterised by unity-in-totality. Through many phenomenological analyses Merleau-Ponty
                       (1962), for example, demonstrated that, although – in the event of an injury to your leg, for
                       example – one is able  to ‘distance’ oneself from  your body, as if it  is something alien to
                       yourself, referring to the pain ‘in your leg’, and so on, it is undeniable that, at a different level
                       of awareness, ‘you’ are in pain, and not just your leg. In short: we don’t just have bodies; we
                       ‘are our bodies’.
   337   338   339   340   341   342   343   344   345   346   347