Page 424 - Deep Learning
P. 424

Notes to Pages 41–45                 407

                explanatory even if the units are not causal laws. I do not claim that explanation
                in terms of chains of component transitions is the only type of explanation, or
                that this concept resolves all issues in the study of scientific explanation, only that
                it accurately represents how change is typically explained in science. Empirical
                data show that it also describes commonsense explanations of biological change
                (Ohlsson, 2002).
              42.  Einstein and Infeld (1938) summarized what they called “the mechanical view”
                in these terms: “In mechanics the future path of a moving body can be predicted
                and its past disclosed if its present condition and the forces acting upon it are
                known. … The great results of classical mechanics suggest that the mechanical
                view can be consistently applied to all branches of physics, that all phenomena
                can be explained by the action of forces representing either attraction or repul-
                sion, depending only upon distance and acting between unchangeable particles”
                (p. 67). In chemistry, the main type of change is the formation and dissolution of
                bonds between atoms: “Dalton’s recognition that a chemical reaction is a process
                in which atoms merely change partners, with reactants one combination of atoms
                and products another combination of the same atoms, is still the all-pervasive
                foundation of explanation in chemistry” (Atkins, 2004, p. 112). This is not to deny
                that at more specific levels of description, the concept of an atomic bond turns
                out to be quite complex (Silvi & Savin, 1994).
              43.  I have not been able to locate a single, conceptual review of all types of erosion
                mechanisms, but Montgomery (2002), Stallard (1995) and Trenhaile (2002) pro-
                vide windows onto the technical literature.
              44.  Suggestions for such single, all-encompassing laws of learning are not lacking;
                see, e.g., Taatgen (2002, 2005).
              45.  Compare the summary of the Gestalt work in Ohlsson (1984a) with Kaplan and
                Simon (1990).
              46.  Compare Abelson’s (1959) and Kelman and Baron’s (1968) lists of modes of conflict
                resolution with those of Chinn and Brewer (1993) and Darden (1992). Although
                these lists do not map onto each other one-to-one, they capture approximately
                the same concepts. Janoff-Bulman (1992) applied these concepts to the resistance
                of trauma patients to their altered circumstances.
              47.  See Anderson and Bower (1973, Chap. 2), for a review of associationism as a psy-
                chological theory.
              48.  Gagné (1965) identified eight types of learning and hence “eight sets of con-
                ditions under which changes in capabilities of the human learner are brought
                about. The implication is that there are eight corresponding kinds of changes
                in the nervous system which need to be identified and ultimately accounted
                for” (p. 57). The view in Ohlsson (2008a) is similar. What has changed over
                time is the conception of the types of learning and (hence) their exact triggering
                conditions.
              49.  For two examples of close analyses of individual learning events, see Schoenfeld,
                Smith and Arcavi (1993) and VanLehn (1991, 1999). D. Kuhn (1995) and Siegler
                and Crowly (1991) have reviewed the so-called microgenetic method in the con-
                text of cognitive development.
   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429