Page 426 - Deep Learning
P. 426

Notes to Pages 55–57                 409

                to conclude when a proposition that was once regarded as true turns out to be
                false after all (non-monotonic logic: see, e.g., Donini et al., 1990 and McDermott
                & Doyle, 1980). In the second half of the 20th century, logic was vitalized by the
                creation of computer programs that operate on logical principles (e.g., Amir &
                Maynard-Zhang, 2004). Logic remains a dynamic field of inquiry after more than
                two millennia of unbroken, cumulative progress (Gabbay & Woods, 2001).
              7.  Pythagoras  was  a  sixth-century  b.c.  Greek  philosopher  and  mathematician.
                The Pythagorean theorem says that in any right-angled triangle, the square of
                the  hypotenuse,  i.e.,  the  side  that  stands  opposite  to  the  right  angle,  is  equal
                to the squares of the other two sides. No text by Pythagoras himself is extant
                and very little is known with certainty about him or his life (Riedweg, 2005).
                Various  proofs  of  the  theorem  are  available  at  http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
                Pythagorean_theorem.
              8.  The proof of Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem was originally published in an
                article titled “Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und
                verwandter Systeme I” which appeared in the journal Monatshefte für Mathematik
                und Physik, 1931, vol. 38, pp. 173–198. An English translation is available in Gödel
                (1962/1992) and in the collection of papers edited by Davis (1965/2004, pp. 5–38).
                Unfortunately,  the  proof  is  too  complicated  and  too  technical  for  others  than
                mathematicians to follow. Nagel and Newman (2001) explain the theorem and
                its proof to nonmathematicians. As one might expect, the application of Gödel’s
                theorem to matters of human cognition is not straightforward; see Lucas (1961)
                and Slezak (1982). My position is that each human being, when operating in a
                deductive, symbol-manipulating mode, as in deliberate, conscious reasoning and
                problem solving, is subject to the Gödel limitation; in that mode, we can, in prin-
                ciple, only reach a subset of all truths. There are two different ways to break out
                of this box: First, because different individuals view the world in slightly differ-
                ent ways, they can be conceptualized, in their deductive mode, as Gödel-limited
                systems with slightly different axioms; collectively, they cover a wider range of
                truths than any single individual. Second, and more fundamental for the the-
                ory of creativity, the cognitive processes of a person are not limited to deduc-
                tive, deliberate thinking. The impact of Gödel’s theorem on cognitive  psychology
                is  thus  to  prove  the  importance  of  nondeductive  processes  such  as  percep-
                tion,  restructuring,  subsymbolic  learning,  etc.  for  creativity.  The  micro-theory
                of creative insight presented in Chapter 4 is consistent with this view.
              9.  Fodor’s argument that one cannot learn a more expressive representational sys-
                tem is developed in more detail than my brief sketch suggests; see Fodor (1976,
                pp. 79–97).
              10.  Not all computational mechanisms are capable of performing every computa-
                tion. If a mental process P maps inputs I = {i 1 , i 2 , i 3 , …, i n } into some output O,
                P(I) = O, then any theory for that process must be capable of computing the
                function that P implements, i.e., of producing O when given I (and nothing else).
                The sufficiency test is a test of the adequacy of a psychological hypothesis, not
                of its truth. A sufficiency test does not prove that a theory is true, only that it
                might, in principle, be true and hence is worth investigating. Theories that do
                not pass the relevant sufficiency test cannot be true and hence can be set aside
   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431